Next Article in Journal
On Computational Hardness of Multidimensional Subtraction Games
Previous Article in Journal
The Modeling of Time Series Based on Least Square Fuzzy Cognitive Map
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Article

EXPTIME Hardness of an n by n Custodian Capture Game

1
Department of Science and Engineering, Tokyo Denki University, Tokyo 120-8551, Japan
2
Graduate School of Advanced Science and Technology, Tokyo Denki University, Tokyo 120-8551, Japan
*
Author to whom correspondence should be addressed.
Current address: Oaza Ishizuka, Hikigun Hatoyama-tyou, Saitama 350-0394, Japan.
These authors contributed equally to this work.
Submission received: 26 January 2021 / Revised: 14 February 2021 / Accepted: 18 February 2021 / Published: 24 February 2021

Abstract

:
Custodian capture occurs when a player has placed two of his pieces on the opposite sides of an orthogonal line of the opponent’s men. Each piece moves like the rook in Chess. Different cultures played it from pre-modern times in two-player strategy board games, Ludus Latrunculorum (Kowalski’s reconstruction), Hasami shogi in Japan, Mak-yek in Thailand and Myanmar, Ming Mang in Tibet, and so on. We prove that a custodian capture game on n × n square board is EXPTIME hard if the first player to capture five or more men in total wins.

1. Introduction

Custodial capture occurs on a square lattice board when a player has placed two of his pieces on the opposite sides of an orthogonal line of the opponent’s men. Different cultures played it in two-player strategy (i.e., perfect information) board games [1,2]. In A History of Chess [3], after introducing Tafl games in Nordic and Celtic, Murray noted that “the method of capture in this game is identical with that in the unknown Latin game Ludus latrunculorum, in the game which Firdawsi attributes to Buzūrjmihr in the Shāhnāma, the Egyptian siga, and a few other Eastern board-games.” His other volume, A History of Board Games other than Chess [4], classified battle games “by, first, the method of capture, beginning with those that employ the interception capture—the oldest form of capture in war games—and, second, by the type of move employed.” A section titled “Games with interception capture and orthogonal moves” introduced Seega in Egypt, Mak-yek in Thailand, Apit-sodok in Malaysia, Hasami-Shogi in Japan, Gala in Sulawesi, and so on. Hasami-Shogi remains still popular among Japanese children.
Although different cultures specified their own rules, this paper takes the following ones:
R.1 
Each player moves one of his pieces in his turn.
R.2 
Each piece may move any orthogonal direction and distance with no obstacle (like the rook in Chess).
R.3 
When a player succeeds in custodial capturing enemy’s men in his turn by moving his piece adjacently next to them, the game removes the men.
R.4 
Repeating sequences of moves are prohibited: if the same position of his men occurs three times, by the same player to move, he must vary his choice to avoid the repetition.
R.5 
The first player to capture enough total number of an opponent’s men throughout the game wins.
They resemble Hasami-Shogi and Ludus latrunculorum (Kowalski’s reconstruction). Maak yék (Captain James Low’s writing [5]) and Ming Mang [6] have similarities in R.2 and R.3. However, the other reconstructions of Ludus Latrunculorum, Tafl games [7], and many others cannot capture multiple men in a line together. These games take the usual starting positions, e.g., placing the all WHITE’s (resp. BLACK’s) men on the lowest (resp. highest) ranks. They often force the game (without R.4) to be a draw since the players may take defensive strategies that never allow the opponent to capture the player’s men.
Once fixing the game rules, combinatorial game theory asks which player to win from the men’s given position on the board. The answer may depend on various board sizes and initial configurations specific to each culture. Computational complexity aims to let ideal game machines (i.e., Turing machines) answer this question for any given board size and initial setup. The future machine could be much faster than the current ones, even solving any finite-size problem in a moment, so it concerns n by n board games rather than the finite board ones interesting for human players. Computational complexity classifies them into the hierarchy PTIME PSPACE EXPTIME EXPSPACE . PTIME is the class of problems solvable in polynomial ( n k ) time, PSPACE polynomial space, EXPTIME exponential ( c n k ) time, and EXPSPACE exponential space (for some constant c > 1 and k > 0 ). For example, Chess [8], Checker [9], and Go (Japanese ko-rule) [10] on n by n board are EXPTIME complete. In other words, a machine for n by n Chess solves any EXPTIME problem by playing Chess starting from a position encoding the problem. Consequently, those games’ best algorithms might be no faster than searching the vast memory holding all possible c n 2 positions of the pieces on n by n board, although EXPTIME ≠ PSPACE is merely a conjecture. One thing for sure is EXPTIME ≠ PTIME, i.e., Chess, Checkers, and Go on n by n board are unsolvable in polynomial time for modern computers. See any computational complexity textbook for more detail, e.g., [11,12].
This paper studies the computational complexity of R.1R.5 under a straightforward winning rule, the winning number of R.5 is five. It can be any number (no smaller than five) but fixed independently of the number of opponent pieces, although most war games set it equal to (or a few less than) that of the opponent’s pieces.
Theorem 1.
The custodian capture game of R.1R.5 on the n × n square board is EXPTIME hard.
Thus, a simple custodian capture game is as hard to play as modern complex games like Chess, Checker, and Go (Japanese ko-rule) on arbitrary board sizes and configurations.
It could be more complicated since R.4 resembles the Chinese ko-rule of Go, prohibiting to return to any position of the pieces on the board that has occurred previously. Chinese ko-rule Go is EXPSPACE by making an archive of all visited places, whose computational complexity lies anywhere between PSPACE [13,14,15,16,17] and EXPSPACE. Theorem 1 proves the complexity of the custodian capture game between EXPTIME and EXPSPACE using R.4 in essential. Some other games, e.g., Chess [8] and Checker [9], enjoy both EXPTIME completeness by allowing repetition and EXPSPACE completeness by prohibiting it [18].

A Proof Outline

Stockmeyer and Chandra [19,20] presented the famous G-series ( G 1 G 6 ) for typical EXPTIME-complete games under log-space many-one reduction. For example, G 2 in Figure 1 proceeds by alternating turns between WHITE and BLACK, permitting WHITE to switch one of his Boolean (TRUTH or FALSE valued) variables ( X 1 or X 2 ) or pass (changing no variable) to make his winning formula W−WIN TRUE. BLACK does it for her variables Y 1 , Y 2 , and formula B−WIN. The first player to make it at the ending of his turn wins. For example, suppose that the G 2 game starts from ( X 1 , X 2 , Y 1 , Y 2 ) = ( FALSE , FALSE , FALSE , TRUE ) and WHITE to move. WHITE switches X 1 : FALSE TRUE to make two ( X 1 and ¬ X 2 ) of the three literals in a term A 3 TRUE while preserving all B terms of the opponent’s 3-term Disjunctive Normal Form (DNF) B 1 B 2 B 3 FALSE even after switching any variable. BLACK responds by Y 1 : FALSE TRUE for making three ( X 1 , ¬ X 2 , and Y 1 ) of the four literals in B 3 TRUE, which is a wrong move since A 3 becomes TRUE; WHITE wins in the next turn by either changing Y 2 or passing. Stockmeyer and Chandra proved that any of the G i games could simulate any EXPTIME problem by adjusting the winning DNFs. Fraenkel and Lichtenstein [8] demonstrated that Chess on n by n board could solve G 3 , so any EXPTIME problem; playing Chess starting from an initial position implementing the G 3 mechanics forces the players to play the G 3 game. The previously known EXPTIME-hardness results relied on one of the G-series [8,9,10,21,22,23]. We establish Theorem 1 by reducing their G 2 game to the custodian capture game on the n × n board with R.1R.5.
Definition 1
( G 2 game). The G 2 game takes τ , W - W I N ( X , Y ) , B - W I N ( X , Y ) , α for a configuration. It consists of a turn player τ { W H I T E ( ) , B L A C K ( ) } making the first move, 12DNF formulae τ - W I N ( X , Y ) representing τ’s winning condition, and an initial boolean assignment α { 0 , 1 } X Y . From disjoint sets X and Y of boolean variables, WHITE can change only those in X, while BLACK can only Y. The game starts from a given configuration and proceeds by alternating turns in which turn player changes at most one of his variables. The first player to satisfy his winning condition at the ending of his turn can win the game.
R.5 allows a player to sum up the numbers of men captured in different places and win, making the number of pieces so far captured part of a game configuration. However, it will never happen in our proof, i.e., the players will win by taking enough men at once.

2. Gadgets in Dead-Lock

R.1 and R.2 of the custodian capture game provide a high degree of freedom to choose whichever men to move toward orthogonal directions and how long-distance with no other men. We will build a configuration of the custodian capture game so that player τ can move none of his men in the initial position, called dead-locked pieces, excepting the only one man, named the free τ. The players must play an escape-and-chase game of moving only their free men. We can build all gadgets (groups of pieces placed on the game board) using W-walls (Figure 2) and its dual B-walls (Figure 3), abbreviated by Figure 4 and Figure 5, respectively. These walls tesselate the entire game board by chess-board symmetry. Although we give only one Figure for each gadget, the game configuration may draw the dual (i.e., swapping ), horizontal, or vertical symmetric images.
Definition 2.
A gadget is dead-locked if so are all belonging men: Moving any τ’s man in it forces τ’s defeat within a few turns.

2.1. Corridors

Figure 6 provides a base gadget to make all other gadgets from its modifications. They fill the entire gameboard by laying the minimum blank squares, the gray zone called a passage, to separate the walls.
Lemma 1.
Figure 6 is dead-locked.
Proof. 
We show that if WHITE releases (i.e., moves) any man dead-locked in Figure 6, he loses immediately. By symmetry, we cover only a few cases. Suppose WHITE releases a wall’s in Figure 7 and captures a single as Figure 8. A neighbor intrudes into the cracked square (i.e., the places becoming empty by custodian capture) in Figure 9 and recaptures more than five in Figure 10. BLACK wins by R.5. If WHITE releases a corner’s piece horizontally, he must soon lose by Figure 11, Figure 12, Figure 13 and Figure 14; Figure 15, Figure 16, Figure 17 and Figure 18 prove the vertical displacement case. □
Figure 6 locates stoppable squares over the crossings Δ, called stops. The free men can move along the passages freely but must halt at only these stops.
Lemma 2.
Figure 6 forces the free men to rest at only the stops.
Proof. 
If the free rests at any non-stop in Figure 19 and captures a single as Figure 20, intrudes into the cracked square in Figure 21, recaptures more than five in Figure 22, and wins. It is the same for the non-stoppable places near corners inside the focuses B and C, as shown in Figure 11, Figure 12, Figure 13, Figure 14, Figure 15, Figure 16, Figure 17 and Figure 18. □

2.2. Obstacles

The corridor may give too much freedom to play any meaningful game. Figure 23 modifies it to block the passages. We call this new gadget an obstacle and abbreviate it in Figure 24. It can pave straight and L-bend routes in Figure 25 and Figure 26.
Lemma 3.
Figure 23 is dead-locked.
Proof. 
If WHITE releases the obstacle’s in Figure 27, comes into the abandoned square (i.e., the place becoming empty by a man’s departure from there) in Figure 28 and wins by capturing many in Figure 29. □

2.3. One-Sided Parking Squares

Figure 30 provides parking squares (displayed by ) at which BLACK can stop but WHITE cannot. We call them B-parking squares, abbreviate it, and the dual in Figure 31 and Figure 32.
Lemma 4.
Figure 30 is dead-locked.
Proof. 
If BLACK releases a left wall’s man in Figure 33, comes into the abandoned square in Figure 34 and wins by capturing five in Figure 35. □
Lemma 5.
Figure 30 forbids the free to rest at any B-parking square.
Proof. 
If the free $ w h rests at a B-parking square in Figure 36 and captures two in Figure 37, intrudes into the cracked yard, recaptures many , and wins in Figure 38 and Figure 39. □

2.4. Weak Points

Obstacles and one-sided parking squares in the previous sections explicitly bound the playing field on the gameboard. On the other hand, τ -weak ones, τ -timers, and τ -magnets in the succeeding ones induce invisible forces bounding the player τ ’s move. Figure 40 is a B-weak point, modifying Figure 6 inside the focus. It contains a checkmate square ⊙. WHITE “checkmates” if he goes there in his turn. We abbreviate it and the dual as in Figure 41 and Figure 42.
Lemma 6.
Figure 40 is dead-locked.
Proof. 
If WHITE releases the right wall’s near the checkmate in Figure 43 and captures a single in Figure 44, comes into the abandoned position in Figure 45, recaptures five , and wins in Figure 46. Similarly, WHITE’s releasing the left wall’s man near the checkmate forces his defeat in Figure 47, Figure 48, Figure 49 and Figure 50. Only these two pieces entail different proofs from those shown in the previous Lemmas. For example, moving the center up by one cell to occupy ⊙ forces BLACK’s defeat in several ways, say (the duals of) Figure 8, Figure 9 and Figure 10 for the corridor, and Figure 27, Figure 28 and Figure 29 for the obstacle. □
Lemma 7.
If WHITE checkmates in Figure 40, he wins.
Proof. 
If WHITE checkmates in Figure 51, WHITE captures one in Figure 52. In the next turn, if does not intrude into the cracked place, will do it and win. Even if does it and recaptures one in Figure 53 and Figure 54, comes into the abandoned square in his second turn, takes many , and wins in Figure 55 and Figure 56. □
Notice that BLACK’s invasion of the checkmating square forces his defeat shown in Figure 57, Figure 58, Figure 59 and Figure 60.

2.5. Timers

Cooperating with W-weak points, B-timers oblige the players to engage in the escape-and-chase game forcing the free to escape and free to chase. A B-timer gadget, Figure 61, consists of a B-weak point in the lower half and an obstacle in the upper one. Only the top and bottom lines change from Figure 40 to add Figure 62’s parking squares inside the focus. The abbreviations, Figure 63 and the dual Figure 64, write an arrow to represent a passage guiding the free to the checkmate ⊙ and a hatched area for a corridor conducting the free to the protector .
Lemma 8.
Figure 61 is dead-locked.
Proof. 
Lemmas 3, 4, and 6 have already shown it for the obstacle, parking squares, and weak-point gadgets, except the following case. The obstruction may invade the B-parking court in Figure 65 (see Figure 62’s ■). It forces WHITE’s defeat in several ways, e.g., Figure 27, Figure 28 and Figure 29 for the obstacle, or Figure 66, Figure 67 and Figure 68 for the B-parking square. □
Lemma 9.
In Figure 61, WHITE’s checkmate forces BLACK’s defeat unless BLACK takes the protector (i.e., moves his free man there) or captures WHITE’s free man in the next turn.
Proof. 
If WHITE checkmates BLACK in Figure 69, BLACK must lose to WHITE’s second move in Figure 70 and Figure 71, unless BLACK strikes back as follows in the next turn: Capture the free and win as in Figure 72, Figure 73 and Figure 74, or take the protector and survive as in Figure 75 and Figure 76 inside C. □
BLACK’s invasion of the checkmating square forces his defeat in Figure 77, Figure 78, Figure 79 and Figure 80 inside the focus B.

2.6. Magnets.

Figure 81 has the twin checkmates ⊙, pulling the free men approaching it and finally catches them and bounds them staying around it. This phenomenon can make a switch gate (see Figure 105) to take only the binary states. We thus call it a W-magnet and abbreviate it and its dual in Figure 82 and Figure 83.
Lemma 10.
Figure 81 is dead-locked.
Proof. 
If WHITE releases the center near the checkmate in Figure 84, comes into the abandoned position and wins in Figure 85 and Figure 86. If BLACK outs the upper wall’s near the checkmate in Figure 87 (resp. the lower wall’s one in Figure 88), comes into there and wins in Figure 89 and Figure 90 (resp. Figure 91 and Figure 92). The other cases reduce to the corridor being dead-locked shown in Lemma 1. □
Lemma 11.
If BLACK takes both checkmates, she wins. If WHITE takes any one of them, he loses.
Proof. 
BLACK takes them and wins by Figure 93 and Figure 94. Meanwhile, if WHITE invades one of them in Figure 95 and captures two in Figure 96, BLACK intrudes into the cracked place and wins in Figure 97 and Figure 98. □

3. Gates

This section provides all gates for proving Theorem 1. In their Figures, ( A , B ) denotes a line passing through two different points A and B, AB ¯ a segment having both endpoints at A and B, and AB : = AB ¯ { A , B } an open piece. Each straight line in figures represents Figure 25’s straight road, whose length may not represent the number of stops therein (except those lines drawing Figure 63’s timer abbreviations). These geometric objects provide sets of stoppable squares (stops and parking squares), written by | S | for their numbers in an object S, and τ = S for τ S .
As already proved in the previous section, the players must move only their free men, so τ { , } often represents the free τ and its standing square in each Figure. We write ( τ , τ ¯ ) = ( A , B ) ( C , D ) to say that ( τ , τ ¯ ) = ( A , B ) , τ is the first to go from A to C, then τ ¯ from B to C in the next turn. When τ ¯ is the first, we should write ( τ ¯ , τ ) = ( B , A ) ( D , C ) , or ( A , B ) ( A , D ) ( C , D ) . If it takes several turns, write ( τ , τ ¯ ) = ( A , B ) * ( C , D ) .
The checkmate squares ⊙ in weak-points, timers, and magnets are the only places where the players can force a win. We refer to these ⊙ by their gadget’s names and measure the distance (i.e., minimum steps) d τ ( A , G ) for τ at A to reach G’s checkmate. Let b τ { 0 , 1 } be the indicator that τ is the first to move. When the free ( τ , τ ¯ ) = ( A , B ) , the free τ ¯ must take one of the following three strategies against τ ’s checkmate at G. Protect G by d τ ¯ ( B , G s protector ) d τ ( A , G ) ; Block G by d τ ¯ ( B , C ) + b τ d τ ( A , C ) for a square C that τ must go through to reach G; Surpass G by d τ ¯ ( B , H ) + b τ d τ ( A , G ) for a τ ¯ ’s checkmate H. If τ ¯ fails all of them, τ ¯ must lose G and the game ( τ wins G and the game), else τ ¯ survives G.
In proving Theorem 1, winning by R.4 is hard to confirm since it must analyze the repetition (a.k.a., cycle, closed-loop) of positions as inevitable. The escape-and-chase game can reduce R.4 to an attack rule R . 4 ˜ : Make a winning repetition. Suppose that the escaper must take the unique winning moves. Immediately after the escaper has visited the same square twice, the chaser will do the same to make a sequence of positions visited only once except the current one twice. The chaser repeats walking the same path several times, forces the escaper first to stop at the same square thrice, and wins R.4. Aida, Crasmaru, Regan, and Watanabe [24] (ACRW) proved that any two-player strategy board game is extendable to another game with all positions possessing the unique winning move for either player. This remarkable result allows us to adopt R . 4 ˜ instead of R.4 for proving Theorem 1.
Definition 3
(unique winning moves). A two-player game with no infinite repetitions divides all possible positions to either player’s winning ones. It has the unique winning moves if each has at most one winning move for either player in the following sense. If a player is the first to move at his winning one, he has only one action leading to his new winning one. If the opponent is the first to move there, all moves lead to the player’s winning positions.
Definition 4
( R . 4 ˜ ). In a two-player board game, a game position is a pair π = ( π τ , π τ ¯ ) of τ’s men’s position π τ and τ ¯ ’s one π τ ¯ . Let # π τ be the number of times that τ’s men have ever visited π τ from the beginning of the game. Repetition is a closed sequence π 1 π k = π 1 of game positions induced by the players’ moves. It is τ ¯ ’s winning one if i , # π i , τ ¯ # π i , τ . If a player succeeds in making his winning repetition by his move, he wins.
Lemma 12.
In any two-player board game with unique winning moves, R.4 implies R . 4 ˜ .
Proof. 
Let π 1 π k = π 1 be a winning repetition that τ ¯ has succeeded in making by revisiting π 1 , τ ¯ : i , # π i , τ ¯ # π i , τ , and # π 1 , τ ¯ < # π 1 , τ before τ ¯ revisits π i , τ ¯ . If τ were a winner, τ ’s unique winning moves would force π 1 π k = π 1 π k = π 1 π k once τ ¯ is willing to repeat the same walk. It certifies τ ’s defeat since τ visits π 1 , τ thrice and violates R.4 before τ ¯ does π 1 , τ ¯ . □
In the current Section 3 except Section 3.6, R . 4 ˜ applies π i to the free men’s position ( , ), although π i must look at all men on the board. Theorem 1’s proof will justify it in the last Section 4.

3.1. One-Way Roads

Figure 25 and Figure 26 are straight and L-bend passages along which the free men can move in both forward and backward directions. One-way roads attach to them B-timers and W-weak points in Figure 99 such that the players must proceed only in the forward direction. WHITE must escape on these one-way roads, and BLACK must chase by the unique alternative moves. We will describe it in Figure 99 (with marks in Figure 100). WHITE must escape along with A → B → D → F, and BLACK must chase him with no delay. Notice that Figure 100 repeats congruently so that LA ¯ and FK ¯ (resp. AB ¯ ) build the congruent gadget with that standing on BD ¯ (resp. DF ¯ ).
Lemma 13.
Suppose | T 1 C | | KG | . Figure 100 forces ( , ) = ( B , A ) ( D , B ) ( F , D ) .
Proof. 
In the first turn, if took ( B , A ) ( BD , A ) , would march ( BD , A ) ( BD , G ) and win for the following reason. It forces WHITE to keep ( K , H ) ( T 1 , C ) for surviving w1 by ¬ ( ( K , H ) ( T 1 , C ) ) d ( , w 1 ) 2 = d ( , T 1 ) . During ( , ) ( KH ¯ { H } , T 1 C ¯ { T 1 } ) { ( T 1 , H ) } , BLACK can protect T1 by d ( , H ) = d ( , T 1 ) 1 , exceed T2 by d ( , w 1 ) 2 < 3 = d ( , T 2 ) , and finally gets an R . 4 ˜ ’s winning repetition ( C , G ) ( T 1 , H ) ( C , G ) . In the repetition, may stop at the parking in T1 (see Figure 61’s □), but can respond it at a stop in KG on the assumption | T 1 C | | KG | , e.g., ( C , G ) ( T 1 , H ) ( T 1 C , KG ) ( C , G ) .
Similarly, the congruent geometry forbids at B to go up or down since the following are equivalent; ( , ) = ( A , ( B , I ) { D } ) in BLACK’s turn forces WHITE’s defeat; ( , ) = ( L , ( G , A ) { B } ) in BLACK’s turn forces WHITE’s defeat. Consequently, must proceed ( B , A ) ( D , A ) , then : ( D , A ) ( D , B ) for surviving T2 by GA ¯ { B } d ( D , T 2 ) = 2 d ( , w 1 ) 3 = d ( , J ) . The same argument brings ( D , B ) ( F , D ) in the second turn since AB ¯ BD ¯ DF ¯ and BD ¯ DF ¯ FK ¯ are congruent. □

3.2. Bridges

A bridge stands over a crossing point of two one-way roads prohibiting the players from changing their directions; they must go straight and never to the left or right. Figure 101 draws a bridge. The players coming from the left (resp. down) must go to the right (resp. up) direction.
Lemma 14.
Suppose | FT 1 | | LO | . Figure 101 forces ( , ) = ( B , A ) ( C , K ) ( F , L ) ( I , H ) ( V , I ) or ( B , A ) ( C , K ) ( F , L ) ( T 1 , O ) ( G , P ) ( I , H ) ( V , I ) .
Proof. 
Similar to Lemma 13’s proof. In the first turn, must proceed ( B , A ) ( C , A ) for surviving w1 by ( C , F ) d ( A , w 1 ) = d ( , T 1 ) = 3 ; Lemma 13 showed could never win the timer on BC. Similarly, : ( C , A ) ( C , K ) for surviving T1 by ( L , R ) d ( C , T 1 ) = 2 < 3 = d ( , w 1 ) = d ( , O ) . Similarly, ( C , K ) ( F , L ) in the second turn.
In the third turn, cannot go backward unless losing w1 as above. The may stick to FT1 to checkmate at T1, but can wait for it in LO on the assumption | FT 1 | | LO | and keep protecting T1 by d ( LO , O ) = d ( FT 1 , T 1 ) = 1 .
In more concrete terms, during ( , ) FT 1 × LO , the men can take each stop at most once, e.g., if { X 1 , X 2 } FT 1 , { Y 1 , Y 2 } LO , and took X1 twice by ( F , L ) ( X 1 , Y 1 ) ( X 2 , Y 2 ) ( X 1 , Y 2 ) , would get an R . 4 ˜ ’s winning repetition ( X 1 , Y 1 ) ( X 2 , Y 2 ) ( X 1 , Y 1 ) . It obliges : ( F , L ) ( G , L ) or ( T 1 , L ) without delay. The former case forces : ( G , L ) ( G , P ) to survive T2 by ( H , W ) d ( G , T 2 ) = 3 < 4 = d ( , U ) . The latter case forces : ( F , L ) ( T 1 , O ) for protecting T1, : ( T 1 , O ) ( G , O ) by R . 4 ˜ , and : ( G , O ) ( G , P ) to survive T2.
In the fourth turn, must go (G, P) → (I, P) for surviving w3 by ( V , I ) d ( P , w 3 ) = d ( , T 2 ) = 3 , and : ( I , P ) ( I , H ) for surviving T2 by HW ¯ { H } d ( I , T 2 ) = 2 d ( , w 3 ) 3 = d ( , U ) .
Once the men reach ( I , H ) , Lemma 13 brings ( , ) = ( I , H ) ( V , I ) . □

3.3. Branches

A branch is a T-junction where the escaper can choose the direction to proceed, to the left or right, by his choice. Figure 102 draws a W-branch, where the players coming from down must go together to either left or right by WHITE’s determination of the directions.
Lemma 15.
Figure 102 forces ( , ) = ( B , A ) ( C , B ) ( D , C ) (to the left) or ( B , A ) ( E , B ) ( F , E ) (to the right) by WHITE’s choice.
Proof. 
Since both the gadgets over AB ¯ BC ¯ CD ¯ and AB ¯ BE ¯ EF ¯ are the one-way roads congruent with that over Figure 100’s AB ¯ BD ¯ DF ¯ , Lemma 13 obliges the free at B to choose ( B , A ) ( C , B ) or ( E , B ) to proceed, whichever induces the claimed subsequent moves. □

3.4. Junctions

Junctions gather the one-way roads multiplied by branches into one. Figure 103 builds it such that the players coming together from either the left or right must go in the upward direction.
Lemma 16.
Suppose | N G | 1 . Figure 103 forces ( , ) = ( B , A ) ( D , B ) ( F , D ) ( Q , F ) (from the left) and ( , ) = ( I , H ) ( L , I ) ( F , L ) ( Q , F ) (from the right).
Proof. 
Similar to Lemma 13’s proof. When they come from the left ( B , A ) , must proceed ( B , A ) ( D , A ) for surviving w1 and w2 by BP { B , D } d ( A , w 1 ) = d ( A , w 2 ) = d ( , T 1 ) = d ( , T 3 ) = 3 d ( , T 4 ) ; Lemma 13 showed could never win T2. Lemma 13 forces : ( D , A ) ( D , B ) .
In the second turn, if went down ( D , B ) ( L , B ) , he would lose as follows. The must respond ( L , B ) ( L , G ) for surviving T5 by BP ¯ { B , G } d ( L , T 5 ) = d ( , w 3 ) = 3 d ( , w 6 ) ; Lemma 13 showed could never win neither T2, T3 nor T4 during ( B , P ) by d ( , V ) 2 = d ( L , T 3 ) , d ( , W ) 3 = d ( L , T 2 ) , and d ( , P ) = 1 < 2 = d ( L , T 4 ) . After that, must take ( L , G ) ( K , G ) for blocking w3, or ( L , G ) ( J , G ) to surpass w3 by d ( J , T 4 ) = 1 < 2 = d ( G , w 3 ) . However, then could march ( { K , J } , G ) ( { K , J } , S ) , protect T4 by d ( S , R ) = d ( { K , J } , T 4 ) = 1 , and win either w3 or w4 by d ( S , w 3 ) = d ( S , w 4 ) = 2 < d ( { K , J } , T 2 ) = d ( { K , J } , T 5 ) = 3 ; Lemma 13 showed could never win either T3 or T4.
If at D went up ( D , B ) ( U , B ) , could march ( U , B ) ( U , G ) , protect T3, and win w3 by Lemma 13. Hence, must proceed ( D , B ) ( F , B ), and Lemma 13 forces : ( F , B ) ( F , D ) , the claimed moves from the left.
When they come from the right ( I , H ) , Lemma 13 forces ( I , H ) ( L , I ) . After that, if took ( L , I ) ( FL { D } , I ) , he would lose to ’s ( FL ¯ { D } , I ) ( FL ¯ { D } , K ) since FL ¯ { D } could never win T3 by d ( K , V ) = 1 d ( , T 3 ) and lose w3 by d ( K , w 3 ) = 2 < d ( , T 2 ) = d ( , T 4 ) = d ( , T 6 ) = 3 . If took (L, I) → (D, I) and got d ( D , T 2 ) = d ( D , T 3 ) = 2 , he would lose as follows. The responds ( D , I ) ( D , K ) to protect both T2 and T3, : ( D , K ) ( C , K ) to survive w3 by ( T 2 , C ) d ( K , w 3 ) = d ( , T 2 ) = 2 , : ( C , K ) ( C , N ) for protecting T2 and : ( C , N ) ( G , N ) to block ’s access to w3; if did not, BP { C , G } would lose w3 by d ( N , w 3 ) = d ( , T 2 ) = 2 d ( , T 1 ) = d ( , T 3 ) . After that, proceeds ( G , N ) ( G , N 1 ) , to the stop N1 NG nearest to G on the assumption | NG | 1 , then ( G , N 1 ) ( ( S , G ) ) ( K , S ) for to keep blocking w3. Finally, wins either w3 or w4, as argued in the second turn of the from-the-left case. Thus, must go ( L , I ) ( F , I ) and Lemma 13 forces : ( L , I ) ( F , L ) , the claimed moves from-the-right. □

3.5. Starts

Starts are the gates where the free men alternate their roles in the escape-and-chase game. Figure 104 is a B-start gate where the free turns from escaper to chaser and the from chaser to escaper.
Lemma 17.
Suppose | O I | = 0 and | L O | | O | . Figure 104 forces ( , ) = ( B , A ) ( D , B ) ( F , C ) ( H , K ) ( , ) = ( P , L ) .
Proof. 
Lemma 13 forces ( B , A ) ( D , B ) , where AB has the gadget congruent with the left’s one on BC. In the second turn, at B can protect both T2 and T3 by d ( B , M ) = 2 and d ( B , J ) = 3 against d ( D , T 2 ) = 2 and d ( D , T 3 ) = 3 , so : ( D , B ) ( F , B ) blocks ’s access to w2 at I and survives by ( F , H ) d ( B , I ) = d ( , I ) = 3 , then : ( F , B ) ( F , C ) to keep protecting T3. Similarly, ( F , C ) ( H , KC ¯ { C } ) in the third turn.
After that, the men may stick to KC and IH . If one man reaches { K , I } , the other must do and make a position ( , ) = ( K , I ) in the next turn for (resp. ) to block ’s (resp. ’s) access to w2 (resp. w3).
After that, to not delay the game, must go immediately to L and beyond by R . 4 ˜ since can wait in O longer than in LO on the assumption | OI | = 0 and | LO | | O | .
Consequently, Lemma 13’s dual forces ( , ) = ( K , I ) ( L , LI ) ( P , L ) . □

3.6. Switches

Figure 105 places men (belonging to no gadget) at stops P, M (as well as R, U, P , M , R , U ) such that a man at P cannot move to any of the left, right, or down directions due to obstacles, and a man at M cannot go to the left, up, or down; M’s invasion to w2 forces his defeat as shown in Figure 77, Figure 78, Figure 79 and Figure 80.
Lemma 18.
The men in Figure 105 are dead-locked except the bounded men on S1M and S2U , who can move only horizontally.
Proof. 
We have already shown all gadgets inside Figure 105 dead-locked. If M’s moved horizontally, P’s would march to w2 and win, so the men standing on M, U, M , U are unmovable. Thus, the men at P, R, P , R are by construction. If the bounded on S1M moved vertically, Lemma 11 would force BLACK’s win by first moving M ’s to the S1’s right side checkmate, and secondly M’s to the other checkmate. □
The at Z moves horizontally to BLOCK the free ’s passing through a W-winning lane crossing at Z . Concretely speaking, Z is one of the stops Z i , s w in Figure 106 (placed at the end of this section). Bounded- standing on Z take five moves to reach the nearest W-weak point w(Z ) in the W-win lane; we write d ( Z , w ( Z ) ) = 5 . All of these G, G , Z, and Z should take a long distance away from the other switch parts.
The left-hand side of Figure 105 configures | S 1 M | = | S 2 U | , | N 1 L | = 0 , | FN 1 | | N 1 | , | BT 1 | | CD | = | IK | (by placing a W-parking on CD), and | CD | + | EN 1 | | N 1 | ; the right-hand side does the same. We make a one-to-one correspondence between S1M and S2U along with E L and write when S 1 M and S 2 U occupy the corresponding places.
We call Figure 105 a W-switch since it takes either the ON or OFF state to check the winning conditions. When WHITE comes there to change between ON and OFF, he swaps the free men with the bounded men. When the free men reach there, we denote them as { f , f } to distinguish from the bounded men { b , b } in the right-hand side of Figure 105. WHITE can choose which men’s sides become the next free men (the remainders are the bounded men). Figure 105 shows an OFF state having ( b , b ) ( S 1 M , S 2 U ) .
Lemma 19.
Suppose WHITE’s move incurs f S 1 M and b S 1 M , BLACK can win by two movements.
Proof. 
Similar to Lemma 18’s proof. If b : E ( F , L ) { E } incurs it, BLACK’s first move is at M to the left checkmate of S1. Lemma 11 forces b to come back ( F , L ) { E } E , presenting BLACK a winning repetition ( E , M ) ( ( F , L ) { E } , S 1 ) ( E , M ) . □
Lemma 20.
Figure 105 for WHITE to move forces either ( f , f , b , b ) = ( E , S 2 U , E , S 2 U ) * ( S 1 M , S 2 U , V , F ) or ( V , F , S 1 M , S 2 U ) , i.e., the switch ON or OFF.
Proof. 
If WHITE will switch ON, he must move ( b , b ) = ( E , Y ) ( F , Y ) for the following reason in any case of Y = L or Y L (i.e., Y S 2 U L ). Any horizontal move b : ( E , Y ) ( X 1 , Y ) , X 1 S 1 M { L } forces WHITE to lose w4 by Y = L d ( L , w 4 ) = 3 4 = d ( X 1 , w 4 ) , or incurring BLACK’s winning repetition by Y L ( b , b ) = ( E , Y ) ( X 1 , Y ) ( X 1 , L ) ( E , L ) ( E , Y ) where the same analysis forces WHITE’s comeback ( X 1 , L ) ( E , L ) . The b could never win T1 against b ’s protection by d ( Y , J ) 3 = d ( E , T 1 ) . R . 4 ˜ forbids b to stay in F N 1 since b can wait for it in N1 on the assumption | N 1 L | = 0 and | F N 1 | | N 1 | . Eventually, b must go to F immediately to not delay the game.
Similarly, BLACK must respond as follows: Y L ( b , b ) = ( F , Y ) ( F , L ) for surviving T2 by d ( F , T 2 ) = 2 < 3 = d ( Y , T 2 s protector ) < 4 = d ( Y , w 4 ) . The Y = L case forces either b ’s vertical move (by the same analysis) or f ’s horizontal one since f ( S 2 , U ) d ( F , T 2 ) = 2 < 1 + 2 = d ( f , ( S 2 , U ) ) + d ( L , T 2 s protector ) .
Lemma 13 makes ( b , b ) = ( F , Y ) ( V , F ) happening in the second turn. The same argument induces ( f , f ) = ( E , L ) * ( V , F ) if WHITE will switch OFF. □
The free men may get into Figure 105 from the left and reach to ( f , f ) = ( A , H ) for changing its state. Notice that the left side of Figure 105 connects to the outside area via Figure 101’s right side structure as ( A , H ) = ( C , K ) .
Lemma 21.
Figure 105 forces ( f , f ) = ( A , H ) ( B , I ) ( C , I K { I } ) or ( A , H ) ( B , I ) ( T 1 , J ) ( C , IK { I } ) .
Proof. 
Similar to Lemma 14’s proof. In the first turn, f must proceed ( A , H ) ( B , H ) to survive w1 by f ( B , C ) d ( H , w 1 ) = 2 d ( , T 1 ) , then f : ( B , H ) ( B , I ) to survive T1 by f ( I , H ) { I } d ( B , T 1 ) = 1 d ( f , w 1 ) 2 = d ( f , J ) . In the second turn, WHITE can choose either ( B , I ) ( T 1 , I ) ( T 1 , J ) ( C , J ) ( C , IK { I } ) or ( B , I ) ( C , I ) ( C , IK { I } ) ; R . 4 ˜ forbids f to stay in BT1 since f can wait for it in IK on the assumption | BT 1 | | IK | . □
Lemma 22.
If WHITE starts Figure 105 from ( f , f ) = ( A , H ) , BLACK can survive.
Proof. 
Suppose WHITE would never choose to move f to EF ¯ { E } or b to E F ¯ { E } ; if WHITE moved f to EF ¯ { E } , f could survive by chasing f aggressively (to the nearest stop of f ) and getting f out of the switch. Then, BLACK wins by making an R . 4 ˜ ’s winning repetition as follows. The assumption | CD | + | EN 1 | | N 1 | allows the following one-to-one correspondence ϕ between the free men’s positions f f : Let N1 contain the disjoint union of N1 c d and N1 e n of cardinalities | CD | and | EN 1 | . T 1 J , C K , CD N 1 c d , EN 1 N 1 e n , and E L . Lemma 21 guides ( f , f ) = ( A , H ) * ( C , K ) . After that, f mimics f ’s move along with ϕ to preserve f = ϕ ( f ) at the beginning of every WHITE’s turn. Similarly, b mimics b ’s one to keep b b (except when BLACK can win immediately due to b ’s wrong move, e.g., if ( f , b ) S 2 U × { L } and b : E G then b can win w4 as shown in Lemma 20).
In the repetition, WHITE could never hope to win T1, T2, T1 , T2 , or w(G) as shown in Lemma 20; f S 1 M { E } forces WHITE to lose w4. He could never win w(G ) since d ( f , L ) d ( f , E ) at the beggining of every WHITE’s turn and d ( b , w 4 ) 4 < 5 d ( b , w ( G ) ) by Figure 106’s construction. Eventually, R . 4 ˜ makes ( f , b , f , b ) = ( E , E , L , L ) happen at the beginning of WHITE’s turn since f can wait for it on N 1 s w , yielding WHITE’s defeat. □
Lemma 23.
If WHITE starts Figure 105 from ( f , f ) = ( A , H ) , WHITE can switch ON or OFF as he likes.
Proof. 
Similar to Lemma 22’s demonstration. Lemma 16 guides ( A , H ) * ( C , J ) ( C , K ) ( D , K ) ( D , Y ) with Y DL { L } { K } , where f must go ( C , J ) ( C , K ) ; R . 4 ˜ forbids f ’s stay in IK since f can wait it in CD on the assumption | CD | = | IK | .
WHITE’s next move depends on either b = E or b E (i.e., b S 1 M { E } ). In the former case, WHITE can move to realize ( f , f , b , b ) = ( D , Y , E , Y ) ( E , Y , E , Y ) ( E , Y 1 , E , Y ) or ( E , Y , E , Y 1 ) * ( S 1 M , S 2 U , V , F ) or ( V , F , S 1 M , S 2 U ) as shown in Lemma 20, where Y S 2 U and ( Y 1 , Y 1 ) ( S 2 U EL ) × ( S 2 U E L ) EL × E L . The latter case is the same by ( f , f , b , b ) = ( D , Y , X , Y ) ( D , Y , E , Y ) ( D , Y 1 , E , Y ) ( E , Y 1 , E , Y ) ( E , Y 1 , E , Y 1 ) * ( S 1 M , S 2 U , V , F ) or ( V , F , S 1 M , S 2 U ) . BLACK may move f twice or b twice to reach ( f , f , b , b ) = ( D , Y , X , Y ) ( D , Y , E , Y ) ( D , Y 1 , E , Y ) ( E , Y 1 , E , Y ) ( E , Y 2 , E , Y ) or ( f , f , b , b ) = ( D , Y , X , Y ) * ( E , Y , E , Y 2 ) , where ( { Y 1 , Y 2 } , { Y 1 , Y 2 } ) ( S 2 U EL ) × ( S 2 U E L ) EL × E L . In any case, Lemma 20 allowed WHITE to switch ON or OFF.
As shown in Lemma 22, BLACK can never hope to win w(Z) nor w(Z ) in these moves since ( f , b , f ) { E } × F L × S 2 U d ( b , E ) + d ( E , T 2 ) = 1 + 3 < 5 = d ( f , w ( Z ) ) and ( f , b , b ) FL × { E } × S 2 U d ( f , E ) + d ( E , T 2 ) = 1 + 3 < 5 = d ( b , w ( Z ) ) by Figure 106’s construction. □
WHITE may choose to enter from the wrong-side entrance of Figure 105, where the right men have already resided, but he cannot defeat BLACK nor change the switch’s state.
Lemma 24.
If Figure 105 starts from ( f , f , b , b ) ( A , H , S 1 M , S 2 U ) in WHITE’s turn, BLACK can survive.
Proof. 
Similar to Lemma 22’s proof. Suppose WHITE would never move f to EF ¯ { E } and prove WHITE to lose. Lemma 21 guides ( f , f ) = ( A , H ) * ( C , K ) ( CD { C } , N 1 ) . The assumption | CD | + | EN 1 | | N 1 | allows f to wait in N1 until R . 4 ˜ (and Lemma 19) force { f , b } ( F , L ) = or ( f , b ) S 1 M × ( B - win - lane { G } ) . The former case forces BLACK to win w4 as shown in Lemma 20, and the latter one does it at w1 by d ( b , ( S 1 , M ) ) = 1 d ( N 1 , w 1 ) = d ( b , w ( G ) ) = 4 = 1 + 3 d ( b , ( S 1 , M ) ) + d ( f , T 1 ) since d ( G , w ( G ) ) = 5 by Figure 106’s construction. The same analysis prohibits WHITE to win w(G), so WHITE must lose by R . 4 ˜ . □
Lemma 25.
Let i = 1 or 2. Suppose Figure 106 starts from ( f , f ) = ( B i , A i ) in WHITE’s turn. If b S 2 s w U s w , ( , ) = ( B i , A i ) * ( V i , I i ) , else WHITE must lose.
Proof. 
When b S 2 s w U s w (i.e., b S 2 s w U s w ), Lemma 14 forces the claimed moves since Figure 106’s gadget over A i B i ¯ B i C i ¯ C i F i ¯ F i G i ¯ G i I i ¯ I i V i ¯ B i K i ¯ K i L i ¯ L i P i ¯ P i H i ¯ is congruent with that in Figure 101.
Suppose b S 2 s w U s w and ( f , f ) = ( B i , A i ) for WHITE to move. The first turn must be ( f , f ) = ( B i , A i ) ( C i , A i ) by Lemma 14. Bounded- can march L s w Z i , s w to block it as ( ( f , f , b ) = ( C i , A i , L s w ) ( C i , A i , Z s w , 1 ) . After that, the f must go to either B i or non-B i and lose to BLACK’s winning repetition ( free , free ) = ( W i , B i ) ( A i , C i ) ( A i , B i ) ( W i , B i ) , or BLACK’s winning position ( A i , C i ) ( A i , C i B i ) ( K i , C i B i ) by Lemma 13. □

3.7. Winning Lanes and Gates

WHITE’s winning lanes are Figure 99’s one-way roads except taking Figure 106’s bridge structures near the switches. WHITE’s winning gates are Figure 40’s B-weak points.

4. Exptime Hardness

Theorem 2
(Theorem 1, formal). The G 2 -game is log-space many-one reducible to the custodian capture game of R.1R.5 over the n × n square board and the winning number five.
Proof. 
We assume that Definition 1’s G 2 -game solves a dichotomy (i.e., no draw) problem in EXPTIME. We prove that the G 2 -game’s winner, say BLACK is the custodial capture game’s one. The same α never appears again in the same player’s turn. Thus, the positions of the bounded men under correspondence also do not do it under correspondence X i = TRUE W - switch [ X i ] = ON and Y i = TRUE B - switch [ Y i ] = ON .
We embed a G 2 game’s configuration by Figure 107’s mapping to the n × n board’s custodian capture game. It combines the W-field on the upper half and the dual B-field on the lower half. We will explain only W-field. It simulates the WHITE’s one turn in the G 2 game by a series of alternating turns in the custodian capture game, beginning from the W-start gate on the left and ending in the B-start gate on the right. The players must mimic an escape-and-chase match (to avoid immediate defeat) and proceed along continuous solid lines. Lemma 14 allows the crossing of the lines with no interference. Lemma 17’s dual starts WHITE’s turn from the W-start gate. At the W-branches above the W-start, Lemma 15 allows WHITE to choose his variable, say X 1 , to change. Lemma 23 changes the state of the W - switch [ X 1 ] (or unchanged by his choice), and Lemma 16 merges the branches at the right W-joins to guide WHITE to the last W-branch above the B-start, where he can declare his win at the end of his turn. The declaration brings him to the top W-branches to pick his winning term, say A 3 in Figure 108, and walk along as described in Figure 109: Visit the right side of the W - switch [ X 1 ] (Figure 105’s Z ), the left side of W - switch [ X 2 ] (Figure 105’s Z), and the right side of the B - switch [ Y 1 ] (the dual Figure’s G ). Lemma 25 passes or blocks the passenger BLACK by the truth value of the literals { X 1 , ¬ X 2 , Y 1 } in A 3 . Consequently, WHITE can win by choosing the TRUE term A i when his winning DNF condition becomes TRUE; WHITE must lose if his choice is wrong.
Notice that Figure 106 may cascade more than two lanes for implementing the WHITE’s 12-term DNF. Alternatively, the two cascades are enough for it by using a branch-switch[ V i , 1 ]-join-branch-switch[ V i , 2 ]-join-⋯ structure, where V i , j is V i ’s occurrence ( V i = X i or Y i ) in a term A j . We can use one of the two W-win lanes to force WHITE to choose the same state over these switches as follows: Let him choose ON or OFF and walk along with the route passing through Z or Z of these X i -switches (G or G of the Y i -switches), respectively, to make sure that the states of these switches are ON (resp. OFF).
Figure 107 maps a G 2 -game instance into the custodian capture game of size O ( | X | + | Y | ) within at most O ( log n ) computational space in the following manner. Each W-switch corresponds to each occurrence of the X-variables. The W-branches on the left towards the W-switches include a binary tree of 2 | X | leaves, where each pair connects to the left and right entrances of a W-switch. Similarly, the right W-junctions form a binary tree of the paired leaves connecting to the W-switches’ exits. Each W-winning lane begins from a B-branch on the top, passing through switches, and ending at a W-victory gate.
Lemmas 1, 3, 4, 6, 8, 10 and 18 demand each player to move only the single free man or one of many bound men. They will justify Lemma 12 to consider only the free and bounded men rather than all men on the board. Lemmas 13–17, 21 and 25 look at only the two free men’s moves in their winning repetitions; Lemmas 19, 20 and 22–24 only the four men inside a single switch. These Lemmas should count the bounded mens’ positions in the other switching gadgets and apply Lemma 12. However, we can justify it as follows and complete the current theorem’s proof.
ACRM proved that any two-person board game might not change the winner even if a turn player allows the opponent (or the game-solving machine) to select the player’s moves to remain just one winning move. Any winning position possesses Definition 3’s unique winning one in the ACRW’s extension of the game. We may assume it for the current custodian capture game as well.
A mini-game starts when ( f , f , b , b ) = ( E , L , E , L ) occurs in one switch and ends when it does in another one. During the mini-game, Let t count the number of moves, π ( t ) = ( π f ( t ) , π b ( t ) ) = ( π f , ( t ) , π f , ( t ) , π b , ( t ) , π b , ( t ) ) be the { free , bounded } × { , } men’s positions at a given time t, and # π ( t ) the number of times visiting the position π from the beginning until the time t of the mini-game. It is a non-decreasing function reset to 0 when a new game starts. Suppose the opponent promises to take the deterministic (predetermined) moves against the player’s unique winning ones. To not delay the game, WHITE should skip π ( t ) π ( t + k ) in a repetition π ( t ) π ( t + 1 ) π ( t + k ) = π ( t ) of his winning positions. Notice that the above Lemmas’ repetitions could never get out the free men from the correponding Figures’ entrances by Lemma 13.
Suppose that BLACK promises to let b mimic b . She moves b to the corresponding place in the same switch each time WHITE has moved b , deducing t , # π b , ( t ) # π b , ( t ) . Lemmas 22 and 24 assure BLACK’s survival over the switches since b b under this promise. The proofs of these Lemmas make b to mimic b and keep b b , too. Consequently, WHITE must choose π = π ( argmax ( t ) ) for argmax ( t ) = max { t | π f ( t ) = π f } during the BLACK’s winning repetitions except when BLACK might be the first to violate R.4. However, b ’s move would never incur it since # π b , ( t ) = 3 occurs only after # π b , ( t ) = 3 in the precedent WHITE’s turn. Similarly, f ’s one would never do it since # π ( t ) # π ( t ) by induction on t as argued in Lemma 12: In a repetition π 1 , f π k , f = π 1 , f π k , f = π 1 , f π k , f with π i , f = π f ( t i + ( j 1 ) k ) at the jth iteration, if 1 i k , # π ( t i ) # π ( t i ) then 1 i k , 1 j 3 , # π ( t i + ( j 1 ) k ) # π ( t i + ( j 1 ) k ) . Consequently, Lemma 12 holds even for the position π ( t ) = ( π f ( t ) , π b ( t ) ) of the two free and all bounded men in the above Lemmas. □

5. Conclusions

We have proved that a custodian capture game over the n × n square board is EXPTIME hard. It allowed for capturing multiple men in a line at once like Japanese Hasami-Shogi. Ludus Latrunculorum, Tafl games, and many others do not, whose computational complexity over n × n board is still unknown. Our proof relied heavily on the no-repetition rule R.4, which might establish even EXPSPACE-completeness by analyzing the bounded men’s trajectories. The custodian capture game allowing repetition of positions might be EXPTIME-complete like Chess [8].

Author Contributions

Conceptualization, T.T.; Formal analysis, T.T., F.I., M.N. and N.K.; Investigation, T.T., F.I., M.N. and N.K.; Methodology, T.T., M.N. and N.K.; Visualization, F.I.; Writing—original draft, T.T., F.I. and N.K.; Writing—review & editing, T.T. All authors have read and agreed to the published version of the manuscript.

Funding

This research received no external funding.

Data Availability Statement

Not applicable.

Conflicts of Interest

The authors declare no conflict of interest.

References

  1. Bell, R.C. Board and Table Games from Many Civilizations; Courier Corporation: Chelmsford, MA, USA, 1979; Volume 1. [Google Scholar]
  2. Parlett, D. The Oxford History of Board Games; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, USA, 1999. [Google Scholar]
  3. Murray, H.J.R. A History of Chess; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 1913. [Google Scholar]
  4. Murray, H.J.R. A History of Board-Games Other than Chess; Clarendon Press: Oxford, UK, 1952. [Google Scholar]
  5. Franklin, M.J. Asiatick Researches, Or, Transactions of the Society Instituted in Bengal, for Inquiring Into the History and Antiquities, the Arts, Sciences, and Literature of Asia; Taylor & Francis: Oxfordshire, UK, 2000; Volume 2. [Google Scholar]
  6. Shotwell, P. A Form of Tibetan Mig-Mang From the West. Available online: https://studylib.net/doc/6753073/a-form-of-tibetan-mig-mang-from-the-west (accessed on 23 February 2021).
  7. Helmfrid, S. Hnefatafl-the Strategic Board Game of the Vikings. Available online: http://hem.bredband.net/b512479/ (accessed on 23 February 2021).
  8. Fraenkel, A.S.; Lichtenstein, D. Computing a perfect strategy for n× n chess requires time exponential in n. J. Combin. Theory Ser. A 1981, 31, 199–214. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  9. Robson, J.M. N by N checkers is Exptime complete. SIAM J. Comput. 1984, 13, 252–267. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  10. Robson, J.M. The complexity of Go. In Proceedings of the IFIP 9th World Computer Congress, Paris, France, 19–23 September 1983. [Google Scholar]
  11. Arora, S.; Barak, B. Computational Complexity: A Modern Approach; Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2009. [Google Scholar]
  12. Hearn, R.A.; Demaine, E.D. Games, Puzzles, and Computation; CRC Press: Boca Raton, FL, USA, 2009. [Google Scholar]
  13. Lichtenstein, D.; Sipser, M. Go is polynomial-space hard. J. ACM (JACM) 1980, 27, 393–401. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  14. Crâşmaru, M.; Tromp, J. Ladders are PSPACE-complete. In Proceedings of the International Conference on Computers and Games, Hamamatsu, Japan, 26–28 October 2000; Springer: Hamamatsu, Japan, 2000; pp. 241–249. [Google Scholar]
  15. Wolfe, D. Go endgames are PSPACE-hard. More Games No Chanc. 2002, 42, 125–136. [Google Scholar]
  16. Saffidine, A.; Teytaud, O.; Yen, S.J. Go Complexities. In Advances in Computer Games; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 2015; pp. 76–88. [Google Scholar]
  17. Zhang, Z. A Note on Computational Complexity of Kill-all Go. arXiv 2019, arXiv:1911.11405. [Google Scholar]
  18. Robson, J.M. Combinatorial games with exponential space complete decision problems. In Proceedings of the International Symposium on Mathematical Foundations of Computer Science, Praha, Czechoslovakia, 3–7 September 1984; pp. 498–506. [Google Scholar]
  19. Chandra, A.K.; Stockmeyer, L.J. Alternation. In Proceedings of the 17th Annual Symposium on Foundations of Computer Science (sfcs 1976), Houston, TX, USA, 25–27 October 1976; pp. 98–108. [Google Scholar]
  20. Stockmeyer, L.J.; Chandra, A.K. Provably difficult combinatorial games. SIAM J. Comput. 1979, 8, 151–174. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  21. Adachi, H.; Kamekawa, H.; Iwata, S. Shogi on n × n board is complete in exponential time. Trans. IEICE 1987, 70, 1843–1852. [Google Scholar]
  22. Zhang, Z. A Note on Hardness Frameworks and Computational Complexity of Xiangqi and Janggi. arXiv 2019, arXiv:1904.00200. [Google Scholar]
  23. Mishiba, S.; Takenaga, Y. QUIXO is EXPTIME-complete. Inf. Process. Lett. 2020, 162, 105995. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  24. Aida, S.; Crasmaru, M.; Regan, K.; Watanabe, O. Games with uniqueness properties. Theory Comput. Syst. 2004, 37, 29–47. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Figure 1. An instance of G 2 .
Figure 1. An instance of G 2 .
Algorithms 14 00070 g001
Figure 2. W-wall.
Figure 2. W-wall.
Algorithms 14 00070 g002
Figure 3. B-wall.
Figure 3. B-wall.
Algorithms 14 00070 g003
Figure 4. W-wall, abbrev.
Figure 4. W-wall, abbrev.
Algorithms 14 00070 g004
Figure 5. B-wall, abbrev.
Figure 5. B-wall, abbrev.
Algorithms 14 00070 g005
Figure 6. Corridor.
Figure 6. Corridor.
Algorithms 14 00070 g006
Figure 7. Wall’s WHITE moves.
Figure 7. Wall’s WHITE moves.
Algorithms 14 00070 g007
Figure 8. WHITE captures.
Figure 8. WHITE captures.
Algorithms 14 00070 g008
Figure 9. BLACK intrudes.
Figure 9. BLACK intrudes.
Algorithms 14 00070 g009
Figure 10. BLACK wins.
Figure 10. BLACK wins.
Algorithms 14 00070 g010
Figure 11. Corner’s WHITE moves horizontally.
Figure 11. Corner’s WHITE moves horizontally.
Algorithms 14 00070 g011
Figure 12. WHITE captures.
Figure 12. WHITE captures.
Algorithms 14 00070 g012
Figure 13. BLACK intrudes.
Figure 13. BLACK intrudes.
Algorithms 14 00070 g013
Figure 14. BLACK wins.
Figure 14. BLACK wins.
Algorithms 14 00070 g014
Figure 15. Corner’s WHITE moves vertically.
Figure 15. Corner’s WHITE moves vertically.
Algorithms 14 00070 g015
Figure 16. WHITE captures.
Figure 16. WHITE captures.
Algorithms 14 00070 g016
Figure 17. BLACK intrudes.
Figure 17. BLACK intrudes.
Algorithms 14 00070 g017
Figure 18. BLACK wins.
Figure 18. BLACK wins.
Algorithms 14 00070 g018
Figure 19. WHITE stops.
Figure 19. WHITE stops.
Algorithms 14 00070 g019
Figure 20. WHITE captures.
Figure 20. WHITE captures.
Algorithms 14 00070 g020
Figure 21. BLACK intrudes.
Figure 21. BLACK intrudes.
Algorithms 14 00070 g021
Figure 22. BLACK wins.
Figure 22. BLACK wins.
Algorithms 14 00070 g022
Figure 23. An obstacle.
Figure 23. An obstacle.
Algorithms 14 00070 g023
Figure 24. An obstacle, abbrev.
Figure 24. An obstacle, abbrev.
Algorithms 14 00070 g024
Figure 25. Straight road.
Figure 25. Straight road.
Algorithms 14 00070 g025
Figure 26. L-bend road.
Figure 26. L-bend road.
Algorithms 14 00070 g026
Figure 27. Obstacle’s WHITE leaves.
Figure 27. Obstacle’s WHITE leaves.
Algorithms 14 00070 g027
Figure 28. BLACK comes in.
Figure 28. BLACK comes in.
Algorithms 14 00070 g028
Figure 29. BLACK wins.
Figure 29. BLACK wins.
Algorithms 14 00070 g029
Figure 30. W-parking.
Figure 30. W-parking.
Algorithms 14 00070 g030
Figure 31. W-Parking, abbrev.
Figure 31. W-Parking, abbrev.
Algorithms 14 00070 g031
Figure 32. B-Parking, abbrev.
Figure 32. B-Parking, abbrev.
Algorithms 14 00070 g032
Figure 33. Parking wall’s BLACK leaves.
Figure 33. Parking wall’s BLACK leaves.
Algorithms 14 00070 g033
Figure 34. WHITE comes in.
Figure 34. WHITE comes in.
Algorithms 14 00070 g034
Figure 35. WHITE wins.
Figure 35. WHITE wins.
Algorithms 14 00070 g035
Figure 36. WHITE stops.
Figure 36. WHITE stops.
Algorithms 14 00070 g036
Figure 37. WHITE captures.
Figure 37. WHITE captures.
Algorithms 14 00070 g037
Figure 38. BLACK intrudes.
Figure 38. BLACK intrudes.
Algorithms 14 00070 g038
Figure 39. BLACK wins.
Figure 39. BLACK wins.
Algorithms 14 00070 g039
Figure 40. B-weak point with a focus.
Figure 40. B-weak point with a focus.
Algorithms 14 00070 g040
Figure 41. B-weak point, abbrev.
Figure 41. B-weak point, abbrev.
Algorithms 14 00070 g041
Figure 42. W-weak point, abbrev.
Figure 42. W-weak point, abbrev.
Algorithms 14 00070 g042
Figure 43. The center right WHITE moves.
Figure 43. The center right WHITE moves.
Algorithms 14 00070 g043
Figure 44. WHITE captures.
Figure 44. WHITE captures.
Algorithms 14 00070 g044
Figure 45. BLACK comes in.
Figure 45. BLACK comes in.
Algorithms 14 00070 g045
Figure 46. BLACK wins.
Figure 46. BLACK wins.
Algorithms 14 00070 g046
Figure 47. The center left WHITE moves.
Figure 47. The center left WHITE moves.
Algorithms 14 00070 g047
Figure 48. WHITE captures.
Figure 48. WHITE captures.
Algorithms 14 00070 g048
Figure 49. BLACK comes in.
Figure 49. BLACK comes in.
Algorithms 14 00070 g049
Figure 50. BLACK wins.
Figure 50. BLACK wins.
Algorithms 14 00070 g050
Figure 51. WHITE checkmates.
Figure 51. WHITE checkmates.
Algorithms 14 00070 g051
Figure 52. WHITE captures.
Figure 52. WHITE captures.
Algorithms 14 00070 g052
Figure 53. BLACK intrudes.
Figure 53. BLACK intrudes.
Algorithms 14 00070 g053
Figure 54. BLACK recaptures.
Figure 54. BLACK recaptures.
Algorithms 14 00070 g054
Figure 55. WHITE’s second turn.
Figure 55. WHITE’s second turn.
Algorithms 14 00070 g055
Figure 56. WHITE wins.
Figure 56. WHITE wins.
Algorithms 14 00070 g056
Figure 57. BLACK invades.
Figure 57. BLACK invades.
Algorithms 14 00070 g057
Figure 58. BLACK captures.
Figure 58. BLACK captures.
Algorithms 14 00070 g058
Figure 59. WHITE intrudes.
Figure 59. WHITE intrudes.
Algorithms 14 00070 g059
Figure 60. WHITE wins.
Figure 60. WHITE wins.
Algorithms 14 00070 g060
Figure 61. B-timer with a focus.
Figure 61. B-timer with a focus.
Algorithms 14 00070 g061
Figure 62. Parking squares.
Figure 62. Parking squares.
Algorithms 14 00070 g062
Figure 63. B-timer, abbrev.
Figure 63. B-timer, abbrev.
Algorithms 14 00070 g063
Figure 64. W-timer, abbrev.
Figure 64. W-timer, abbrev.
Algorithms 14 00070 g064
Figure 65. WHITE invades.
Figure 65. WHITE invades.
Algorithms 14 00070 g065
Figure 66. WHITE captures.
Figure 66. WHITE captures.
Algorithms 14 00070 g066
Figure 67. BLACK intrudes.
Figure 67. BLACK intrudes.
Algorithms 14 00070 g067
Figure 68. BLACK wins.
Figure 68. BLACK wins.
Algorithms 14 00070 g068
Figure 69. WHITE checkmates.
Figure 69. WHITE checkmates.
Algorithms 14 00070 g069
Figure 70. WHITE’s second move.
Figure 70. WHITE’s second move.
Algorithms 14 00070 g070
Figure 71. WHITE wins.
Figure 71. WHITE wins.
Algorithms 14 00070 g071
Figure 72. WHITE checkmates.
Figure 72. WHITE checkmates.
Algorithms 14 00070 g072
Figure 73. BLACK captures it.
Figure 73. BLACK captures it.
Algorithms 14 00070 g073
Figure 74. BLACK wins.
Figure 74. BLACK wins.
Algorithms 14 00070 g074
Figure 75. WHITE checkmates.
Figure 75. WHITE checkmates.
Algorithms 14 00070 g075
Figure 76. BLACK protects it.
Figure 76. BLACK protects it.
Algorithms 14 00070 g076
Figure 77. BLACK invades.
Figure 77. BLACK invades.
Algorithms 14 00070 g077
Figure 78. BLACK captures.
Figure 78. BLACK captures.
Algorithms 14 00070 g078
Figure 79. WHITE intrudes.
Figure 79. WHITE intrudes.
Algorithms 14 00070 g079
Figure 80. WHITE wins.
Figure 80. WHITE wins.
Algorithms 14 00070 g080
Figure 81. W-magnet.
Figure 81. W-magnet.
Algorithms 14 00070 g081
Figure 82. W-magnet, abbrev.
Figure 82. W-magnet, abbrev.
Algorithms 14 00070 g082
Figure 83. B-magnet, abbrev.
Figure 83. B-magnet, abbrev.
Algorithms 14 00070 g083
Figure 84. The center WHITE leaves.
Figure 84. The center WHITE leaves.
Algorithms 14 00070 g084
Figure 85. Black comes in.
Figure 85. Black comes in.
Algorithms 14 00070 g085
Figure 86. BLACK wins.
Figure 86. BLACK wins.
Algorithms 14 00070 g086
Figure 87. The upper BLACK leaves.
Figure 87. The upper BLACK leaves.
Algorithms 14 00070 g087
Figure 88. The lower BLACK leaves.
Figure 88. The lower BLACK leaves.
Algorithms 14 00070 g088
Figure 89. WHITE comes in.
Figure 89. WHITE comes in.
Algorithms 14 00070 g089
Figure 90. WHITE wins.
Figure 90. WHITE wins.
Algorithms 14 00070 g090
Figure 91. WHITE comes in.
Figure 91. WHITE comes in.
Algorithms 14 00070 g091
Figure 92. WHITE wins.
Figure 92. WHITE wins.
Algorithms 14 00070 g092
Figure 93. BLACK checkmates.
Figure 93. BLACK checkmates.
Algorithms 14 00070 g093
Figure 94. BLACK wins.
Figure 94. BLACK wins.
Algorithms 14 00070 g094
Figure 95. WHITE invades.
Figure 95. WHITE invades.
Algorithms 14 00070 g095
Figure 96. WHITE captures.
Figure 96. WHITE captures.
Algorithms 14 00070 g096
Figure 97. BLACK intrudes.
Figure 97. BLACK intrudes.
Algorithms 14 00070 g097
Figure 98. BLACK wins.
Figure 98. BLACK wins.
Algorithms 14 00070 g098
Figure 99. One-way road.
Figure 99. One-way road.
Algorithms 14 00070 g099
Figure 100. One-way road with marks.
Figure 100. One-way road with marks.
Algorithms 14 00070 g100
Figure 101. Bridge.
Figure 101. Bridge.
Algorithms 14 00070 g101
Figure 102. W-branch.
Figure 102. W-branch.
Algorithms 14 00070 g102
Figure 103. Junction.
Figure 103. Junction.
Algorithms 14 00070 g103
Figure 104. B-start.
Figure 104. B-start.
Algorithms 14 00070 g104
Figure 105. W-switch OFF.
Figure 105. W-switch OFF.
Algorithms 14 00070 g105
Figure 106. W-win lanes crossing with W-switch.
Figure 106. W-win lanes crossing with W-switch.
Algorithms 14 00070 g106
Figure 107. Custodian capture game for G 2 .
Figure 107. Custodian capture game for G 2 .
Algorithms 14 00070 g107
Figure 108. An instance of G 2 .
Figure 108. An instance of G 2 .
Algorithms 14 00070 g108
Figure 109. W-winning lanes.
Figure 109. W-winning lanes.
Algorithms 14 00070 g109
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Ito, F.; Naito, M.; Katabami, N.; Tsukiji, T. EXPTIME Hardness of an n by n Custodian Capture Game. Algorithms 2021, 14, 70. https://0-doi-org.brum.beds.ac.uk/10.3390/a14030070

AMA Style

Ito F, Naito M, Katabami N, Tsukiji T. EXPTIME Hardness of an n by n Custodian Capture Game. Algorithms. 2021; 14(3):70. https://0-doi-org.brum.beds.ac.uk/10.3390/a14030070

Chicago/Turabian Style

Ito, Fumitaka, Masahiko Naito, Naoyuki Katabami, and Tatsuie Tsukiji. 2021. "EXPTIME Hardness of an n by n Custodian Capture Game" Algorithms 14, no. 3: 70. https://0-doi-org.brum.beds.ac.uk/10.3390/a14030070

Note that from the first issue of 2016, this journal uses article numbers instead of page numbers. See further details here.

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop