Next Article in Journal
Bifuzzy-Bilevel Programming Model: Solution and Application
Next Article in Special Issue
Quantum Fields as Category Algebras
Previous Article in Journal
Design of a Long-Pass Filter with Effects on Fluorescence Image Observation for Surgical Fluorescence Microscope Applications
Previous Article in Special Issue
Symmetry of Dressed Photon
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Article

Categorical Nonstandard Analysis

1
Nagahama Institute of Bio-Science and Technology, Shiga 526-0829, Japan
2
Independent Reseacher, Tokyo 103-0008, Japan
*
Author to whom correspondence should be addressed.
Submission received: 30 July 2021 / Revised: 21 August 2021 / Accepted: 23 August 2021 / Published: 26 August 2021
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Quantum Fields and Off-Shell Sciences)

Abstract

:
In the present paper, we propose a new axiomatic approach to nonstandard analysis and its application to the general theory of spatial structures in terms of category theory. Our framework is based on the idea of internal set theory, while we make use of an endofunctor U on a topos of sets S together with a natural transformation υ , instead of the terms as “standard”, “internal”, or “external”. Moreover, we propose a general notion of a space called U -space, and the category U S p a c e whose objects are U -spaces and morphisms are functions called U -spatial morphisms. The category U S p a c e , which is shown to be Cartesian closed, gives a unified viewpoint toward topological and coarse geometric structure. It will also be useful to further study symmetries/asymmetries of the systems with infinite degrees of freedom, such as quantum fields.

1. Introduction

Nonstandard analysis and category theory are two of the great inventions in foundation (or organization) of mathematics . Both of these have provided productive viewpoints to organize many kinds of topics in mathematics or related fields [1,2]. On the other hand, a unification of the two theories is yet to be developed, although there are some pioneering works, such as [3].
In the present paper, we propose a new axiomatic framework for nonstandard analysis in terms of category theory. Our framework is based on the idea of internal set theory [4], while we make use of an endofunctor U on a topos of sets S together with a natural transformation υ , instead of the terms as “standard”, “internal”, or “external”.
The triple ( S , U , υ ) is supposed to satisfy two axioms. The first axiom (“elementarity axiom”) introduced in Section 2 states that the endofunctor U should preserve all finite limits and finite coproducts. Then, the endofunctor U is viewed as some kind of extension of functions preserving all elementary logical properties. In Section 3, we introduce another axiom (“idealization axiom”), which is the translation of “the principle of idealization” in internal set theory and proves the appearance of useful entities, such as infinitesimals or relations, such as “infinitely close”, in the spirit of Nelson’s approach to nonstandard analysis [4].
Section 4 is devoted to provide a few examples of applications on topology (on metric spaces, for simplicity). Although the characterizations of continuous maps or uniform continuous maps in terms of nonstandard analysis are well known, we prove them from our framework for the reader’s convenience. In Section 5, we characterize the notion of a bornologous map, which is a fundamental notion in coarse geometry [5].
In Section 6, we introduce the notion of U -space and U -morphism, which are the generalizations of examples in the previous two sections. We introduce the category U S p a c e consisting of U -spaces and U -morphisms, which is shown to be Cartesian closed. This will give a unified viewpoint toward topological and coarse geometric structure, and will be useful to study symmetries/asymmetries of the systems with infinite degrees of freedom, such as quantum fields.

2. Elementarity Axiom

Let S be a topos of sets, i.e., an elementary topos with a natural number object satisfying well-pointedness and the axiom of choice (See [1], which is based on the idea in [6]). We make use of an endofunctor U : S S with a natural transformation υ : I d S U satisfying two axioms, “elementarity axiom”, and “idealization axiom”.
Elementarity Axiom: U preserves all finite limits and finite coproducts.
Remark 1.
U does not necessarily preserve power sets. This is the reason for the name of “elementarity”.
It is easy to see that “elementarity axiom” implies the preservation of many basic notions, such as elements, subsets, finite cardinals (in particular, the subobject classifier 2), and propositional calculi. Moreover, the following theorem holds.
Theorem 1.
U is faithful.
Proof. 
It preserves diagonal morphisms and complements. □
Theorem 2.
For any element x : 1 X , υ X ( x ) = U ( x ) υ 1 .
Proof. 
By naturality of υ. □
Corollary 1.
All components of υ are monic.
From the discussion above, a set X in S is to be considered as a canonical subset of U ( X ) through υ X : X U ( X ) . Hence, U ( f ) : U ( X 0 ) U ( X 1 ) can be considered as “the function induced from f : X 0 X 1 through υ .”
Definition 1.
Let A , B be objects in S . The function e v A , B : A × B A B satisfying
e v A , B ( a , f ) = f ( a )
for all ( a , f ) A × B A is called the evaluation (for A , B ) . The lambda conversion g ^ : Z Y X of g : X × Z Y is the function satisfying
g = e v X , Y ( 1 X × g ^ ) ,
where 1 X × g ^ denotes the function satisfying
( 1 X × g ^ ) ( x , z ) = ( x , g ^ ( z ) ) .
We define a family of functions κ A , B : U ( B A ) U ( B ) U ( A ) in S by the lambda conversion of U ( e v A , B ) : U ( A × B A ) U ( A ) × U ( B A ) U ( B ) .
The theorem below means that κ A , B υ B A represents “inducing U ( f ) from f through υ ” in terms of exponentials.
Theorem 3.
Let f : A B be any function in S . Then,
κ A , B υ B A ( f ^ ) = U ( f ) ^ .
(Here, ^ denotes the lambda conversion operation.)
Proof. 
Take the (inverse) lambda conversion of the left hand side of the equality to be proved. It is e v U ( A ) , U ( B ) ( i d U ( A ) × κ A , B ) ( i d U ( A ) × υ B A ) ( i d U ( A ) × f ^ ) . By the naturality of υ and functorial properties of U , it is calculated as follows:
Symmetry 13 01573 i001
 □
Corollary 2.
κ A , B υ B A is monic.
Notation 1.
From here, we omit υ and κ. U ( f ) : U ( X ) U ( Y ) will be often identified with f : X Y and denoted simply as f instead of U ( f ) .
Theorem 4.
Let P : X 2 be any proposition (function in S ). Then,
x X P ( x ) x U ( X ) P ( x ) .
Proof. 
P : X 2 factors through “true : 1 2 if and only if P : U ( X ) 2 factors thorough “true : 1 2 . □
Dually, we obtain the following:
Theorem 5.
Let P : X 2 be any proposition (function in S ). Then,
x X P ( x ) x U ( X ) P ( x ) .
The two theorems above are considered as the simplest versions of “transfer principle”. To treat with free variables and quantification, the theorem below is important. (The author thanks Professor Anders Kock for indicating this crucial point.)
Theorem 6.
U preserves images.
Proof. 
As U preserves all finite limits, it preserves monics. On the other hand, it also preserves epics since every functor preserves split epics and every epic in S is split epic (axiom of choice). Hence, the image, which is nothing but the epi-mono factorization, is preserved. □

3. Idealization Axiom

From our viewpoint, nonstandard Analysis is nothing but a method of using an endofunctor, which satisfies the “elementarity axiom” and the following “idealization axiom”. The name is after “the principle of idealization” in Nelson’s internal set theory [4]. Most of the basic ideas in this section have much in common with [4], although the functorial approach is not taken in internal set theory.
Remark 2.
Internal set theory (IST) is a syntactical approach to nonstandard analysis consisting of the “principle of Idealization (I)” and the two more basic principles, called “principle of Standardization (S)” and “Transfer principle (T)”. In our framework, the role of (S) is played by the axiom of choice for S , and (T) corresponds to the contents of Section 2.
Notation 2.
For any set X, X ˜ denotes the set of all finite subsets of X.
Idealization Axiom: Let P be an element of U ( 2 X × Y ) . Then,
x X ˜ y U ( Y ) x x P ( x , y ) y U ( Y ) x X P ( x , y ) .
Or dually,
Idealization Axiom, dual form: Let P be an element of U ( 2 X × Y ) Then,
x X ˜ y U ( Y ) x x P ( x , y ) y U ( Y ) x X P ( x , y ) .
When X is a directed set with an order ≤ and P U ( 2 X × Y ) satisfies the “filter condition”, i.e.,
x 0 X ( P ( x 0 , y ) x X ( x x 0 P ( x , y ) ) ) ,
or dually, the “cofilter condition”, i.e.,
x 0 X ( P ( x 0 , y ) x X ( x 0 x P ( x , y ) ) ) ,
then “idealization axiom” is simplified as the “commutation principle”:
Theorem 7
(Commutation Principle). If P U ( 2 X × Y ) satisfies the “filter condition” and “cofilter condition” above, respectively, and then
x X y U ( Y ) P ( x , y ) y U ( Y ) x X P ( x , y )
and
x X y U ( Y ) P ( x , y ) y U ( Y ) x X P ( x , y )
holds, respectively.
By the principle above, we can easily prove the existence of “unlimited numbers” in U ( N ) , where all arithmetic operations and order structure on N are naturally extended.
Theorem 8
(Existence of “unlimited numbers”). There exists some ω U ( N ) such that n ω for any n N .
Proof. 
It is obvious that, for any n N , there exists some ω N U ( N ) such that n < ω . □
As in S , we can construct rational numbers and the completion of them as usual, we have the object R , the set of real numbers. Then, we obtain the following:
Corollary 3.
“Infinitesimals” do exist in U ( R ) . That is, there exists some r U ( R ) such that | r | < R for any positive R R .

4. Topological Structure: Continuous Map and Uniform Continuous Map

We will take an example of basic applications of nonstandard analysis within our framework, i.e., the characterization of continuity and uniform continuity in terms of a relation ≈ (“infinitely close”) on U ( X ) , which is based on essentially the same arguments that are well-known in nonstandard analysis—particularly, internal set theory [4]. For simplicity, we will discuss only for metric spaces here. (For more general topological spaces, we can define ≈ in terms of the system of open sets. See [4] for example.)
Definition 2
(Infinitely close). Let ( X , d ) be a metric space. We call the relation ≈ on U ( X ) defined below as “infinitely close”:
x x ϵ R d ( x , x ) < ϵ .
That is, d ( x , x ) is infinitesimal. It is easy to see that ≈ is an equivalence relation on U ( X ) .
Theorem 9
(Characterization of continuity). Let ( X 0 , d 0 ) , ( X 1 , d 1 ) be metric spaces and 0 , 1 be infinitely close relations on them, respectively. A map f : X 0 X 1 is continuous if and only if
x X 0 x U ( X 0 ) ( x 0 x f ( x ) 1 f ( x ) )
holds.
Proof. 
We can translate the condition for f by using the usual logic, “commutation principle”, and “transfer principle” as follows:
x X 0 x U ( X 0 ) ( x 0 x f ( x ) 1 f ( x ) ) x X 0 x U ( X 0 ) ( δ R d 0 ( x , x ) < δ ϵ R d 1 ( f ( x ) , f ( x ) ) < ϵ ) x X 0 x U ( X 0 ) ϵ R δ R ( d 0 ( x , x ) < δ d 1 ( f ( x ) , f ( x ) ) < ϵ ) x X 0 ϵ R x U ( X 0 ) δ R ( d 0 ( x , x ) < δ d 1 ( f ( x ) , f ( x ) ) < ϵ ) x X 0 ϵ R δ R x U ( X 0 ) ( d 0 ( x , x ) < δ d 1 ( f ( x ) , f ( x ) ) < ϵ ) x X 0 ϵ R δ R x X 0 ( d 0 ( x , x ) < δ d 1 ( f ( x ) , f ( x ) ) < ϵ ) .
 □
Theorem 10
(Characterization of uniform continuity). Let ( X 0 , d 0 ) , ( X 1 , d 1 ) be metric spaces and 0 , 1 be infinitely close relations on them, respectively. A map f : X 0 X 1 is uniformly continuous if and only if
x U ( X 0 ) x U ( X 0 ) ( x 0 x f ( x ) 1 f ( x ) )
holds.
Proof. 
We can translate the condition for f by using usual logic, “commutation principle” and “transfer Principle” as follows:
x U ( X 0 ) x U ( X 0 ) ( x 0 x f ( x ) 1 f ( x ) ) x U ( X 0 ) x U ( X 0 ) ( δ R d 0 ( x , x ) < δ ϵ R d 1 ( f ( x ) , f ( x ) ) < ϵ ) x U ( X 0 ) x U ( X 0 ) ϵ R δ R ( d 0 ( x , x ) < δ d 1 ( f ( x ) , f ( x ) ) < ϵ ) ϵ R x U ( X 0 ) x U ( X 0 ) δ R ( d 0 ( x , x ) < δ d 1 ( f ( x ) , f ( x ) ) < ϵ ) ϵ R δ R x U ( X 0 ) x U ( X 0 ) ( d 0 ( x , x ) < δ d 1 ( f ( x ) , f ( x ) ) < ϵ ) ϵ R δ R x X 0 x X 0 ( d 0 ( x , x ) < δ d 1 ( f ( x ) , f ( x ) ) < ϵ ) .
 □
As we have seen, a morphism between metric spaces is characterized as “a morphism with respect to ≈”. This suggests the possibility for considering other kinds of “equivalence relations on (some subset of) U ( X ) ” as generalized spatial structures on X. In the next section, we will take one example related to large scale geometric structure.

5. Coarse Structure: Bornologous Map

Let us consider another kind of equivalence relation ∼ (“finitely remote”) defined below. For simplicity, we will discuss only for metric spaces here.
Definition 3
(Finitely remote). Let ( X , d ) be a metric space. We call the relation ∼ on U ( X ) defined below as “finitely remote”:
x x R R d ( x , x ) < R .
Note that we use ∃ instead of ∀, in contrast to “infinitely close”. This kind of dual viewpoint will be proven to be useful in the geometric study of large scale structures, such as coarse geometry [5].
In fact, we can prove that a “bornologous map”, a central notion of a morphism for coarse geometry, can be characterized as “a morphism with respect to ∼”, similar to how (uniform) continuity can be viewed as “a morphism with respect to ≈”.
Definition 4
(Bornologous map). Let ( X 0 , d 0 ) and ( X 1 , d 1 ) be metric spaces. A map f : X 0 X 1 is called a bornologous map when
R R S R x X 0 x X 0 ( d 0 ( x , x ) < R d 1 ( f ( x ) , f ( x ) ) < S )
holds.
Theorem 11
(Characterization of bornologous map). Let ( X 0 , d 0 ) , ( X 1 , d 1 ) be metric spaces and 0 , 1 be finitely remote relations on them, respectively. A map f : X 0 X 1 is bornologous if and only if
x U ( X 0 ) x U ( X 0 ) ( x 0 x f ( x ) 1 f ( x ) )
holds.
Proof. 
We can translate the condition for f by using the usual logic, “commutation principle”, and “transfer principle” as follows:
x U ( X 0 ) x U ( X 0 ) ( x 0 x f ( x ) 1 f ( x ) ) x U ( X 0 ) x U ( X 0 ) ( R R d 0 ( x , x ) < R S R d 1 ( f ( x ) , f ( x ) ) < S ) x U ( X 0 ) x U ( X 0 ) R R S R ( d 0 ( x , x ) < R d 1 ( f ( x ) , f ( x ) ) < S ) R R x U ( X 0 ) x U ( X 0 ) S R ( d 0 ( x , x ) < R d 1 ( f ( x ) , f ( x ) ) < S ) R R S R x U ( X 0 ) x U ( X 0 ) ( d 0 ( x , x ) < R d 1 ( f ( x ) , f ( x ) ) < S ) R R S R x X 0 x X 0 ( d 0 ( x , x ) < R d 1 ( f ( x ) , f ( x ) ) < S ) .
 □

6. The Notion of U -Space and the Category U Space

Based on the characterizations of topological and coarse geometrical structure, we introduce the notion of U -space.
Definition 5
( U -space). A U -space is a triple ( X , K , ) consisting of a set X, a subset K of U ( X ) , which includes X as a subset, and a preorder ⇝ defined on K.
When the preorder ⇝ is an equivalence relation, i.e., a preorder satisfying symmetry, we call the U -space symmetric. A symmetric U -space ( X , K , ) is called uniform if K = U ( X ) . The “infinitely close” relation and the “finitely remote” relation provide the simplest examples of uniform U -space structure.
Actually, any topological space X with the set of open sets T can be viewed as U -space ( X , U ( X ) , ) where x x denotes the preorder “ O T x U ( O ) x U ( O ) ”. If ( X , T ) is a Hausdorff space, we can construct the symmetric U -space ( X , K , ) , where K denotes
K = { x U ( X ) | x 0 X x x }
and x x is defined as the relation “ x 0 X x 0 x & x 0 x .” The transitivity of ⇀ follows from the fact that if ( X , T ) is Hausdorff, x 0 x and x 0 x imply x 0 = x 0 for all x 0 , x 0 X . In fact, the preorder ⇝ becomes an equivalence relation.
The concept of U -space will provide a general framework to unify various spatial structure, such as topological structure and coarse structure. The notion of morphism between U -spaces is defined as follows:
Definition 6
( U -spatial morphism). Let ( X 0 , K 0 , 0 ) and ( X 1 , K 1 , 1 ) be U -spaces. A function f : X 0 X 1 is called a U -spatial morphism from ( X 0 , K 0 , 0 ) to ( X 1 , K 1 , 1 ) when f ( K 0 ) K 1 and
x 0 x f ( x ) 1 f ( x )
holds for any x , x K 0 .
The uniform continuous maps and bornologous maps between metric spaces are nothing but U -spatial morphisms between corresponding uniform U -spaces. The notion of continuous maps between Hausdorff spaces can be characterized as U -spatial morphisms between the corresponding symmetric U -spaces.
Definition 7
(Category U S p a c e ). The category U S p a c e is a category whose objects are U -spaces and whose morphisms are U -spatial morphisms.
Definition 8.
Let ( X 0 , K 0 , 0 ) and ( X 1 , K 1 , 1 ) be U -spaces. The U -space ( X 0 × X 1 , K 0 × K 1 , ) , where the preorder ⇝ is defined as
( x 0 , x 1 ) ( x 0 , x 1 ) x 0 0 x 0 & x 1 1 x 1 ,
is called the product U -space of ( X 0 , K 0 , 0 ) and ( X 1 , K 1 , 1 ) .
Theorem 12.
The projections become U -spatial morphisms. The diagram consisting of two U -spaces, the product space of them, and projections becomes a product in U S p a c e .
Proof. 
Easy. □
Definition 9
(Exponential U -space). Let ( X 0 , K 0 , 0 ) and ( X 1 , K 1 , 1 ) be U -spaces. We denote the set of all U -spatial morphisms from X 0 to X 1 as [ X 1 X 0 ] , which is the subset of X 1 X 0 . The restriction of e v X 0 , X 1 : X 0 × X 1 X 0 X 1 onto X 0 × [ X 1 X 0 ] X 1 is denoted as [ e v X 0 , X 1 ] . The U -space ( [ X 1 X 0 ] , K , ) , where K is defined as the subset of U ( [ X 1 X 0 ] ) ,
K = { f | x K 0 [ e v X 0 , X 1 ] ( x , f ) K 1 and x 0 x [ e v X 0 , X 1 ] ( x , f ) 1 [ e v X 0 , X 1 ] ( x , f ) }
and ⇝ is defined as
f f x K 0 [ e v X 0 , X 1 ] ( x , f ) 1 [ e v X 0 , X 1 ] ( x , f ) ,
is called the exponential U -space from ( X 0 , K 0 , 0 ) to ( X 1 , K 1 , 1 ) .
Theorem 13.
Let ( X 0 , K 0 , 0 ) and ( X 1 , K 1 , 1 ) be U -spaces and ( [ X 1 X 0 ] , K , ) be the exponential U -space from ( X 0 , K 0 , 0 ) to ( X 1 , K 1 , 1 ) . The morphism [ e v X 0 , X 1 ] : X 0 × [ X 1 X 0 ] X 1 , the restriction of e v X 0 , X 1 , is a U -spatial morphism. Moreover, it becomes an evaluation in U S p a c e and [ X 1 X 0 ] is an exponential in U S p a c e .
Proof. 
First, we prove that [ e v X 0 , X 1 ] is a U -spatial morphism: For any ( x , f ) K 0 × K , [ e v X 0 , X 1 ] ( x , f ) is in K 1 since x K 0 and f K . Suppose that ( x , f ) , ( x , f ) K 0 × K and ( x , f ) ( x , f ) , that is, x , x K 0 , f , f K , x x and f f . Then, we have
[ e v X 0 , X 1 ] ( x , f ) [ e v X 0 , X 1 ] ( x , f )
since f f . We also have
[ e v X 0 , X 1 ] ( x , f ) [ e v X 0 , X 1 ] ( x , f )
since f K . Hence, [ e v X 0 , X 1 ] ( x , f ) [ e v X 0 , X 1 ] ( x , f ) .
Next, we prove that [ e v X 0 , X 1 ] : X 0 × [ X 1 X 0 ] X 1 becomes an evaluation in U S p a c e , and [ X 1 X 0 ] is an exponential in U S p a c e : Let ( X 2 , K 2 , 2 ) be any U -space and f : X 0 × X 2 X 1 be any U -spatial morphism. Consider the lambda conversion f ^ : X 2 X 1 X 0 . By assumption that f is U -spatial,
( x , c ) , ( x , c ) K 0 × K 2 & ( x , c ) ( x , c ) f ( x , c ) , f ( x , c ) K 1 & f ( x , c ) 1 f ( x , c )
holds, where ⇝ denote the preorder on K 0 × K 2 . It is equivalent to the statement that c , c K 2 and c 2 c implies that
x , x K 0 & x 0 x f ^ ( c ) ( x ) , f ^ ( c ) ( x ) K 1 & f ^ ( c ) ( x ) 1 f ^ ( c ) ( x ) .
Applying the implication above for the case c = c X 2 , we have f ^ ( c ) [ X 1 X 0 ] . Hence, we can replace f ^ : X 2 X 1 X 0 with [ f ^ ] : X 2 [ X 1 X 0 ] by restricting the codomain to the image of f ^ . Moreover, we can also prove that [ f ^ ] is U -spatial from the implication: By the implication above, we have [ f ^ ] ( c ) , [ f ^ ] ( c ) K and [ f ^ ] ( c ) [ f ^ ] ( c ) when c , c K 2 and c 2 c . This means that [ f ^ ] is U -spatial.
It is easy to show that this [ f ^ ] is the unique U -spatial morphism from X 2 to [ X 1 X 0 ] satisfying [ e v X 0 , X 1 ] ( 1 X 0 × [ f ^ ] ) = f . This completes the proof. □
Combining the two theorems above, we have:
Theorem 14.
The category U S p a c e is a Cartesian closed category.

Author Contributions

Conceptualization, H.S. and J.N.; Investigation, H.S. and J.N.; Methodology, H.S.; Writing—original draft, H.S.; Writing—review & editing, J.N. All authors have read and agreed to the published version of the manuscript.

Funding

This work was partially supported by Research Origin for Dressed Photon, JSPS KAKENHI (grant number 19K03608 and 20H00001) and JST CREST (JPMJCR17N2).

Institutional Review Board Statement

Not applicable.

Informed Consent Statement

Not applicable.

Acknowledgments

The authors would like to express their sincere thanks to Anders Kock and Edward Nelson for their encouragements. They are grateful to Hiroshi Ando, Izumi Ojima, Kazuya Okamura, Misa Saigo, Hiroki Sako, and Ryokichi Tanaka for the fruitful discussions and comments.

Conflicts of Interest

The authors declare no conflict of interest.

References

  1. MacLane, S. Categories for the Working Mathematician, 2nd ed.; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany; New York, NY, USA, 1998. [Google Scholar]
  2. Robinson, A. Non-Standard Analysis; North Holland: Amsterdam, The Netherlands, 1966. [Google Scholar]
  3. Kock, A.; Mikkelsen, J. Topos-theoretic factorization of nonstandard extensions. In Victoria Symposium on Nonstandard Analysis; Lecture Notes in Mathematics; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 1974; Volume 369, pp. 122–143. [Google Scholar]
  4. Nelson, E. Internal set theory: A new approach to nonstandard analysis. Bull. Am. Math. Soc. 1977, 83, 1165–1198. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
  5. Roe, J. Lectures on Coarse Geometry; University Lecture Series; American Mathematical Society: Providence, RI, USA, 2003; Volume 31. [Google Scholar]
  6. Lawvere, W. Elementary Theory of the Category of Sets. Proc. Nat. Acad. Sci. USA 1964, 52, 1506–1511. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Saigo, H.; Nohmi, J. Categorical Nonstandard Analysis. Symmetry 2021, 13, 1573. https://0-doi-org.brum.beds.ac.uk/10.3390/sym13091573

AMA Style

Saigo H, Nohmi J. Categorical Nonstandard Analysis. Symmetry. 2021; 13(9):1573. https://0-doi-org.brum.beds.ac.uk/10.3390/sym13091573

Chicago/Turabian Style

Saigo, Hayato, and Juzo Nohmi. 2021. "Categorical Nonstandard Analysis" Symmetry 13, no. 9: 1573. https://0-doi-org.brum.beds.ac.uk/10.3390/sym13091573

Note that from the first issue of 2016, this journal uses article numbers instead of page numbers. See further details here.

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop